Saturday, October 8, 2022

Really, really old models of Adamic origins

Young Earth Creationist (YEC) thinkers believe most if not all species in the Homo genus comprise the species of Adam (e.g. herehere, but see a contrasting view here), and at least some Intelligent Design proponents seem to agree (see the chapter on human fossils here). These are the arguments for and against for such a position:

For:

Adam and his descendants need to be completely different from anything that came before them, not just in terms of cognitive capacities but also anatomy. Even the earliest members of the Homo genus have a suite of anatomical features that look completely different from the ape-like creatures that existed before them. Furthermore, different species with the Homo genus differ only slightly. As such, the genus seems to comprise a tightly similar unit of human-like creatures that are unlike anything that came before, which respects the traditional intuition about human uniqueness. The YEC Marvin Lubenow in his Bones of Contention argued as such, so did ID theorist Casey Luskin in his chapter in the Science and Human Origins. Perhaps the most sophisticated defense of the view comes from the YEC Todd Wood, who claims to demonstrate evidence of "biological discontinuity" between Homo and non-Homo species based on a trait-based clustering method (see some of his latest stuff here, and responses to criticisms here). Wood claims his analysis is compelling and robust, since they reveal the same pattern of clustering regardless of which fossil trait datasets or statistical tools are used.

Against:

Humanness necessitates two things - human-like cognitive abilities, and anatomical similarities. The further back we place Adam, the more difficult it gets to defend the idea that his earliest descendants demonstrated cognitive capacities found in modern humans. Not unsuccessful, to be sure, but difficult. Similarly, the more different Adam and his earlier descendants look from us, the harder it becomes to say that they were humans.

Personally, I'm more sensitive to the arguments against this model than the ones in favor of it. For example, Ian Tattersall claims the definition of Homo is a vestige of old-time taxonomy, where systematists felt the need to place everything in either the Australopithecus basket or the Homo one. If that is true, it becomes more contentious to claim that the earliest members of the Homo genus would have anything to do with modern humans.

Maybe a more direct disproof of this view would come from the anthropological research conducted by Gregory Forth who, based on his analysis of testimonies given by indigenous people of Flores, comes to the remarkable conclusion that Homo floriensis are either still alive, or were alive until recently (book, interview). For our purposes, the relevant bit of his research is that the people of Flores almost unequivocally classify these creatures as being non-human. I think that testimony is really powerful, since probably the most compelling criteria of humanness is I know it when I see it.

I'm curious why, despite such potential problems with this model, it continues to be popular. I suspect the most recent book on YEC paleontology also argues for this view.

Maybe it's because the argument for the view - the necessity for biological discontinuity - is seen to be a far more powerful consideration than those against. After all, it's probably difficult to show that earliest hominins did not have modern-type cognition. One of these days I want to do a thorough investigation of the model.

Sunday, October 2, 2022

Andrew Loke: How to affirm radical human uniqueness yet not risk scientific falsifiability

Continuing our series on investigating the "limit scenarios" of human evolution, today we have Andrew Loke's book The Origin of Humanity and Evolution: Science and Scripture in Conversation. For those looking to buy the book, let me just say that virtually all of the material relevant to human origin model-building is found in chapters 5 and 6, and even there a lot of the discussion is relevant only to Christian-specific concerns like interpreting Genesis, original sin and the Fall, etc. Make of that what you will.

Recap

Going back to our "traditional intuitions" about human origins outlined in the last post:

1. Unique properties. Adam and his descendants - the "humans" if you will - have properties that were never had by any other biological creature. Usual candidates of such properties include language or symbolic thought, particular spiritual propensities, perhaps a different physical constitution as well.

2. Unique ancestry. All descendants of Adam trace their lineage uniquely to Adam and Eve, with no interbreeding with non-Adamic creatures. None of us are 95% Adam and 5% something else.

3. Ancient humans are modern humans. All of us - all of Adam's offspring - had and have abilities that made Adam unique - language, advanced cognitive skills, religion, culture, and the human "look". There might be differences between them, but all of his children would be immediately recognizable as human.

4. Recentness. Adam and Eve were ancient, but probably not very ancient - they had some connection with the rest of humanity's history that followed them.

While Swamidass' contributions were useful for points 3 and 4, Loke's contributions are most useful for point 1. To recap, by replacing the "unique ancestry" requirement with "genealogical ancestry", Swamidass was able to demonstrate that the common ancestor of all currently living humans could be located pretty recently in history, as recently as perhaps six to fifteen thousand years ago. I think even a 50,000 year old Adam would respect our intuitions #3 and #4. The question then becomes, by pushing back the date for the universal common ancestor, can we also reduce the amount of Adamic-non-Adamic interbreeding that happened, and still respect population genetics considerations? One suspects that if the extent of such interbreeding is low enough - say just the occasional contacts between two groups not unlike human-Jinn cohabitations - it might become theologically palatable. That's really the big question Swamidass' analysis leaves us with.

Loke's contributions

Loke's big coup, on the other hand, has been to argue that we can get away with quite a bit of uniqueness in Adam and his descendants, and yet not run into scientific difficulties. What are such scientific difficulties? Well, if Adam and his descendants suddenly "leapt into the scene" with unique capacities, it's plausible to believe such an event would leave some kind of a mark on history and/or archaeology. Indeed, the Reasons to Believe ministry posits such abruptness as a prediction of an Adamic origins model (at least in their older model). If that is the case, then this is certainty scientifically falsifiable. Vincent Torley, for example, goes through ten plausible candidates of what sets Adam apart from non-Adamic creatures, and argues that none of those features show any evidence of abrupt emergence in history. Rather, they all seem to have appeared gradually, with no particular privileged point in history that could be identified as signifying de novo emergence. Secondly, if Adam did indeed have unique biological properties, faithfully passing on those properties to his descendants via biological reproduction might cause difficulties, especially if we also want to maintain that his descendants occasionally interbred with non-Adamic hominins. I don't know if there's any mileage to this argument, but it's one more possible point of contact with scientific evidence.

How does one get around these problems? Following Loke, we can posit Adam-specific capacities that are (i) thin enough that they would not necessarily leave a mark on history, (ii) significant enough that it nonetheless respects intuition #1, and (iii) posited to be a feature of the soul, not the body, so not biologically tractable.

For Loke, the special feature of Adam and his descendants (the imago dei, to use equivalent Christian terminology) consists of a vocation bestowed by God, and a set of capacities that make such a vocation possible. Such capacities could include: (i) the capacity to implement "a unique kind of dominion that could extend to the whole world and over all kinds of creatures", (ii) "a sense of responsibility towards
the Creator God and other creatures for this kind of dominion", and (iii) "becoming conformed to Christ", the non-Christian equivalent might be some other elevated spiritual property. Furthermore, he posits such difference doesn't even have to be qualitative:
"[D]ifference in degree is an ontological difference, and one can suggest a possible scenario in which the uniqueness of human beings lies in the fact that only they have the degree of capacity to demonstrate the kind of unique dominion and responsibility to God explained earlier and are elected by God for the role of royal representatives."
Finally, such capacities can be said to be a feature of the soul, so we wouldn't need to rely on genetics or biological reproduction to faithfully equip each child of Adam with them. Loke outlines mechanisms of how souls are passed on to offspring, but I don't think that question is particularly contentious. As Muslims, we believe each individual child is bestowed with a new soul at a point in their embryological development; and that's how each child of Adam would have received these properties.

Evaluation

1. What were Adam's capacities, really? While Loke's proposal is certainly interesting, I'm left somewhat unsatisfied by the fact that he doesn't really flesh out his account of human specialness. For example, what does the ability to "exercise a unique kind of dominion" mean? On the face of it, and at the risk of being reductive, it sounds like Adam and his descendants would have greater problem-solving skills - they'd be able to extend their reaches to the furthest corners of the planet and beyond, in a way no other biological creature could. If that's the case, then it's not clear why such a property couldn't be biologically tractable.

In his defense, his project is to put forward a model that could, for all we know, be true. So the mere possibility of falsifiability doesn't threaten his case. That might actually be a good point - in defending human uniqueness, maybe we should not aim for complete scientific intractability, just for it to be "thin enough" that it lies outside the streetlight of scientific investigation. So even though Loke's description of human capacities leave a lot unstated, as long as it is thin enough to not have a significant biological footprint, we should concede the success of his project. This also means his model can fend off any objection Vincent Torley can throw at him.

2. Can we add in more ways in which Adam was unique? Perhaps the most popular suggestion for Adam's uniqueness is the capacity of language or symbolic thought, with spiritual responsibility being a close second. I think this is the next natural step for Loke's project: can we expand his conception of Adam's uniqueness by adding in these properties, while retaining scientific plausibility?

This leads to two important questions worth pursuing in the longer run:

(i) Can we attribute capacities of language use/symbolic thought to the soul?
(ii) If Adam and his descendants were uniquely gifted with language, should we expect an archaeological footprint corresponding to their emergence?

In his essay in The Soul Hypothesis, linguist Mark Baker suggests human linguistic capacity is irreducible to the physical, and to my non-expert ears, it seems like Chomsky and Berwick's view is at least reminiscent of this position. However, it seems like the latter's answer to the second question is a strong "yes", which brings us to the problem of scientific falsifiability. Interestingly, the "lack of archaeological remains" is a problem faced by scientists who ascribe human-like cognitive capacities to Neandertals and other hominins as well. They take refuge in the incompleteness of the archaeological record, and perhaps a similar strategy can be available for proponents of thicker forms of human uniqueness as well. This is a strategy Loke himself adopts in defending a more ancient date of Adam's origin. Again, as long as we're trying to tell a story that's not unfalsifiable in principle, but only in actuality, such a move might succeed.

Religious sensibilities is an interesting question in its own right, and I suspect similar issues would be relevant there as well.

3. Problems of interbreeding. If someone opts for Adamic-non-Adamic interbreeding to deal with problems of population genetics, but at the same time wants to preserve thick forms of human uniqueness, we would run into the problem of Adam's children cohabiting with creatures that were unlike us in significant ways. Loke speculates on the possibility of Cain marrying into a non-Adamic hominin family:
[I]t is plausible to think that Cain’s wife could, indeed, enter into a primitive marriage relation, play a primitive role of a mother and wife, speak and communicate in primitive languages like Cain; the only thing she would lack would be one/some or all of the ‘image of God’ properties mentioned previously. . . On the other hand, Cain’s role in marriage and family life and his communicative abilities might have been quite primitive as well; after all, the earlier mentioned capacities had only just begun to be realized. Thus the differences in behaviour between Cain and his wife might not have been very great, though the differences might still have caused difficulties and thus such a relationship would not have been ideal (unlike the case of an ideal helper for Adam, see previous discussion).
I suspect this is an important motivation for maintaining a sufficiently thin concept of human uniqueness, which doesn't encompass "big" properties like use of language. This is yet another reason why it's important to investigate the extent of interbreeding required to hold off the population genetics objections. If the children of Adam cohabited with non-Adamic humans who were nonetheless quite different from them, it doesn't seem like this could've been a very regular occurrence. It seems to maintain the joint occurrence of thick human uniqueness and interbreeding, the extent of the latter would need to be significantly constrained; which, in turn, raises the question of whether that amount of interbreeding can make sense of the population genetics data.

It is important to note, however, that interbreeding and human uniqueness don't come in the same package. Even if interbreeding places constraints on certain forms of human uniqueness, Loke's contributions still remain important in their own right. We can try to develop a model without interbreeding (if we can solve the population genetics-based objections in other ways), while affirming strong views of human uniqueness along similar lines.

Sunday, September 25, 2022

Joshua Swamidass on human origins: Give me interbreeding, I'll give you a recent Adam

Widely shared intuitions about human origins

Picture me, a normal Muslim, with traditional, down-the-line intuitions about religion. If you happened to ask me about the origin of Adam (peace be upon him) or humanity, I'd want to affirm the following loosely phrased things:

1. Unique properties. Adam and his descendants - the "humans" if you will - have properties that were never had by any other biological creature. Usual candidates of such properties include language or symbolic thought, particular spiritual propensities, perhaps a different physical constitution as well.

2. Unique ancestry. All descendants of Adam trace their lineage uniquely to Adam and Eve, with no interbreeding with non-Adamic creatures. None of us are 95% Adam and 5% something else.

3. Ancient humans are modern humans. All of us - all of Adam's offspring - had and have abilities that made Adam unique - language, advanced cognitive skills, religion, culture, and the human "look". There might be differences between them, but all of his children would be immediately recognizable as human.

4. Recentness. Adam and Eve were ancient, but probably not very ancient - they had some connection with the rest of humanity's history that followed them.

I know these theses are vague, but that's by design, because the intuitions themselves are somewhat vague. I don't have a precise theological intuition about, for example, how recent Adam and Eve would have had to live, or how old would've been too old for comfort. Also, all of this is on top of the explicit facts of scripture, like Adam and Eve having been created miraculously in paradise, sent down to earth, all of us tracing our lineage to them, and Adam and his descendants having a special honor bestowed upon them. Furthermore, if I want to tell a story of Adam and/or humanity's origins, I'd want that to be broadly consistent with the empirical facts. I don't want to account for discrepancies between this story and the data by appealing to ad hoc theory-saving miracles. This forms the fifth item on my list of wants:

5. No ad hoc miracles. An internally and externally coherent story about the origin of humanity through Adam and Eve might contain miracles, but those need to be situated in appropriate theological contexts.

Concepts like "consistency with empirical facts" and "theologically appropriate miracles" are super hard to pin down, and I plan to dedicate essay-length treatments to each of these issues. But for now, let's take these five somewhat ambiguous yet widely shared intuitions as our point of departure in trying to build a model of human origins.

The ideal view of human origins

Let's also interpret the theses as constituting spectra, not binaries. For example, Adam and his descendants have unique properties (intuition #1), but they might have very many or very few of them. On one end, they might represent a completely different species of creatures in terms of their biology and cognitive abilities. On the other, they might be nigh indistinguishable from some of the other extant creatures on earth, except in some subtle but important ways. While both possibilities respect the "unique properties" intuition, the former does so to a greater extent than the latter. Similarly for the rest of the theses. Our ideal Adamic origins model would posit humans as being:

  • As different in their properties and abilities from the rest of the biological creatures as possible,
  • With as close to zero interbreeding with non-humans as possible,
  • With the most ancient members looking and acting as similar to those of us living today as possible,
  • Emerging at as recent a date as possible,
  • Invoking as few ad hoc miracles as possible.

Of course, empirical research can push against items in this wishlist. For example, people have claimed that given the amount of genetic diversity present among humans alive today, the ancestor to all humanity - without allowing for interbreeding - must have lived more than half a million years ago. Let's say the empirical claim there is accurate, and we really feel strongly about not allowing any interbreeding, so we put Adam and Eve that far back. That scores really high with intuition #2, but kind of complicates intuitions #3 and #4. If humanity started half a million years ago, we must also admit that the earliest children of Adam looked (and possibly acted) considerably different than modern humans that are around today. That difference might be minute enough to not cause any discomfort (maybe their psychology and cognitive capacities were on par with us, with some minor differences), but it might also be huge enough to be a dealbreaker (maybe language, the hallmark characteristic of humans, didn't even emerge that far back. Chomsky et al claim language arose in Homo sapiens in the last couple hundred years at most). The significance of that difference is a matter of empirical research.

On the other hand, let's say we feel really strongly about Adam having to be really similar to behaviorally modern humans, so we want to place him during or after the period where strong archaeological evidence of human culture begins to emerge, say in the past 50,000 years. This respects intuitions #3 and #4, but might cause issues with #2 - since this date is way too recent to accommodate all of the extant genetic diversity (and other population genetic issues, like human-Neandertal interbreeding, geological separation of populations, etc.). On this model, we might have to either accept some degree of interbreeding between Adamic and non-Adamic creatures, or appeal to miracles. It also raises potential problems with intuition #1, since non-Adamic hominins living 50,000 years ago might be said to be pretty similar to modern humans in terms of their cognitive capacities.

I hope this demonstrates how empirical data can, at least potentially, press on where we want to locate a historical Adam. Too recent might mean modern, recognizable humans but with possible interbreeding, but too old means no interbreeding but ambiguously human.

This delineates pretty clearly the ideal model of human origins Muslims would want to defend - one that respects as many of the traditional intuitions as possible. In the process, there might be trade-offs between intuitions, and we'd need to judge which intuitions are more important than others. Personally, for example, I don't think "recentness" is a very important intuition to rescue, so I'd be happy with an old Adamic origin date as long as the rest of the intuitions are respected. Other Muslims might have different intuitions.

Limit scenarios of human origins

For example, recently there's been some discussion on whether some of these traditional intuitions are warranted by a straightforward reading of scripture. The most important contribution on the topic has been from David Solomon Jalajel, whose work (or an earlier version thereof) I've evaluated on this blog (it's due for a major re-write). The idea seems to be the following: when one reads the relevant scriptural excerpts at face value, it doesn't seem to necessitate either the first, second or fourth intuitions. It does suggest that all currently living humans originated from an initial, miraculously created pair, but it doesn't say that we are unique in terms of our ontology or capacities, or that Adamic humans never interbred with non-Adamic creatures. If that's true, that would mean we can get away with a fairly recent origin of humans. As expected, this view has received considerable criticism. As I've mentioned in my previous article on the topic, I am quite hesitant to accept parts of his thesis, especially the idea that Adam is not our exclusive ancestor.

As part of our quest to build the best model of human origins, however, I think it's useful to evaluate scenarios that question such traditional intuitions as well. With that thought in mind, in the next month (or beyond, depending on progress) I'll be attempting to evaluate such non-traditional models of human evolution. Other than Jalajel's essay, at least three other books have been published on the topic by Shoaib Ahmed Malik, Joshua Swamidass, and Andrew Loke. The latter two books are written from a Christian perspective and therefore have details Muslims would consider irrelevant, but they also discuss, and attempt to rescue, at least some of the traditional intuitions mentioned above. I will also include William Lane Craig's recent book as representing a contrary view, which takes all but the recentness intuition as theologically valuable.

It is very important to note at the outset, however, that my evaluation of such models is not an endorsement of them. Rather, this should be the very first step in our explorations (basically, "how much can we get away with", scripturally speaking). Even if these models proves successful, we should attempt to nonetheless rescue the other traditional intuitions to see how many readings of scriptures can be consistently defended in light of the data.

Joshua Swamidass: as recent as you want

With that said, here are my brief thoughts on Joshua Swamidass' book The Genealogical Adam and Eve: The Surprising Science of Universal Ancestry. As mentioned above, the book contains a lot of details that are at best of tangential relevance to the Muslim, like issues of original sin, the fall, or a very recent date of human emergence. My goal here is to extract the points of particular benefit to the Muslim project.

In my opinion, the big coup of Swamidass' work is as follows.

Using pre-published (plus his own) mathematical simulations, he shows that if we allow a sufficiently loose definition of ancestry, then the "common ancestor" of all humans can be located fairly recently in time - as recently as six to fifteen thousand years ago. What is this loose definition of ancestry? According to Swamidass, to say X and Y are my ancestors is simply to say, X and Y contributed to my lineage at some point, or alternatively, I can trace my lineage back to X and Y. On this view, if an offspring of X and Y had babies with someone from a different population Z, then all the resulting offspring themselves can claim to have descended from X and Y, even though they don't have exclusive ancestry from X and Y - there's quite a lot of Z mixed in.

For a more extreme illustration still, let's say an X-Y offspring ends up in a remote island populated by people Z, where they intermarry with the locals and have children. These children themselves mix with the rest of the Z islanders, and eventually after generations have passed, all inhabitants of the island end up having some share of the lineage of the initial X-Y offspring. In this situation, the entire island population can claim to have descended from X and Y, even though the entirety of the ancestral input was just from one X-Y individual. The analogy Swamidass has for this sort of ancestry is that of an explosion - the more it spreads, the more powerful and all-consuming it becomes. On such a view of ancestry, it's not particularly difficult to see how all of humanity living on earth can trace their lineage back to a common ancestor just a few thousand years ago. Even remote, geographically isolated island populations pose no threat to this view, since all it would take for that population to be caught up in the web of ancestry is for one boat from the mainland to make it to the island every once in a while.

Applied to the question of Adamic origins, Swamidass' story is that humans as a group may have evolved independently from ape-like ancestors, but Adam and Eve - also humans - were chosen or created miraculously. They married and produced children, who in turn went on to have children with non-Adamic humans, until eventually all people on earth were tangled in the Adamic ancestry in just a few thousand years. Allowing for such a story, we can envision Adam and Eve living pretty recently.

Importantly, note the propositions that are entailed by his model, and the ones that are not - Swamidass' account does not require Adam and Eve to be recent, or to be exactly like the rest of non-Adamic humans (and therefore not being unique in any way). All he is saying is that both recent or old origins are possible, and if we really do want to locate Adam and Eve at a recent date - we have a significant amount of freedom.

Points of benefit

How can these insights be of benefit to a Muslim? For one, Swamidass feels the need to defend a very, very recent Adam to make sense of certain Biblical passages, while a Muslim is not under such constraints. Even if we want to defend the recentness intuition, we can very well place Adam 50,000 years ago or earlier, and posit the looser definition of ancestry to account for the "too much genetic diversity" problem. This move might have other virtues - for example, we can identify Adam and his children as having unique capacities, like behavioral modernity, which arose upwards of 50,000 years ago. On this model, by sacrificing intuition #2, we are potentially securing #1, #3 and #4.

Of course, all of this is premised on whether his definition of ancestry is one Muslims can accept. We will have occasion to explore this in more detail when I review the other books I referenced above, which are more theologically inclined than that of Swamidass. The unique benefit of the Swamidass' work, again, is that it allows us maximal freedom to place Adam pretty much as recently as needed, and that might be beneficial especially while conjoined to other virtues.

One sticking point for me, however, is that ancestry is kind of treated as a zero-sum thing in the book. For example, a Muslim might be very opposed to the sort of extreme, explosive definition of ancestry proposed by Swamidass, but they might nonetheless accept a more restricted form of interbreeding. Our scholars discussed the possibility of Jinn-human interbreeding, and Arab folk tales mention some tribes deriving their lineage from the Jinn; meaning some limited interbreeding here and there might not be cause for theological concern. Furthermore, I suspect a Muslim might also be accepting of the possibility that limited bestial interbreeding might have occurred between the children of Adam and non-Adamic creatures. As long as such events are rare and/or unintended, just the mere possibility of interbreeding might not raise immediate red flags. Some Christians share this intuition as well. Given this fact, it would've been useful to know if his findings would change if there were limited episodes of interbreeding. Put differently, how would his date estimates change with increasing or decreasing degree of interbreeding? Would it mean the collapse of the entire model, or just require pushing the date back by a few tens of thousands of years? An answer to that question might've led to retrieving ground around the second intuition as well.

Either way, I think Swamidass' book is a good way to start thinking about such "limit scenarios" of human evolution. I'm picking up Andrew Loke's book next.

Sunday, July 17, 2022

Review of Muntasir Zaman's "The Height of Prophet Adam": Towards a universal framework for resolving conflicts between science and scripture

I recently finished writing a comprehensive constructive review of Mufti Muntasir Zaman's recent book, The Height of Prophet Adam: At the Crossroads of Science and Scripture. I think it's one of the most important works in Islamic intellectual discourse, which is why I felt the need to really do a deep dive into it. My essay is available on my new academia.edu page. Here's the abstract and table of contents:

Abstract

In his recently published book "The Height of Prophet Adam: At the Crossroads of Science and Scripture", Mufti Muntasir Zaman comprehensively addresses the putative conflict between, on one hand, Prophetic hadiths stating that humans on Earth started off ninety feet tall and then gradually decreased; and on the other, what modern science deems possible on the matter. The scope of the book is wider than just this one putative conflict, however: even for those who do not think this is an issue worth taking seriously, it is still valuable as a demonstration of how to systematically address conflicts between science and hadith. In this review, I attempt to first provide what I think is an improved version of the Mufti’s solution to the problem, relying almost exclusively on the resources and analytic tools presented in the book itself. I then comment on aspects of the Mufti’s treatment that require modification, particularly his handling of a Divine intervention explanation of giant humans on early earth. Finally, I briefly comment on how the Mufti’s approach can be modified into a tentative universal framework for handling science-hadith conflicts in general.

Table of contents

Section no.

Section title

1

Introduction

1.1

Significance of the book

1.2

Structure of the review

2

The proposed framework and implementation

2.1

Framework for resolving science-scripture conflicts

2.2

The book’s implementation of the framework

3

Evaluating the narrations

3.1

Epistemic categories of hadiths

3.2

Evaluating the epistemic weight of the hadiths

3.2.1

The hadiths in question

3.2.2

Disclaimers about the assessment of hadith probability

3.2.3

Four issues with the narrations reporting Adam’s height being sixty cubits

3.2.4

Two additional issues with the narrations reporting humankind gradually decreasing in length

4

Constructing a Solution

4.1

Harmonization – Can the hadith be interpreted differently?

4.2

Maybe the decreasing height narration is unreliable?

4.2.1

Reasons for considering the narration unreliable

4.2.2

Reasons for considering the narration reliable

4.3

“Reliable” hadiths are reliable to a probabilistic degree

4.3.1

Hadith narrations as probabilistic reports

4.3.2

Some low-probability “reliable” hadiths might not have been Prophetic

4.3.3

Completing the solution

4.4

Suspending judgment and taking stock of evidence base

5

Points of disagreement

5.1

Prioritization as a strategy to solve science-hadith conflicts

5.1.1

What is prioritization?

5.1.2

Why this type of prioritization is inadequate

5.1.3

Comparison between prioritization and appealing to probabilistic nature of narrations

5.2

Problems with “settling the science”

5.2.1

Scientific impossibility of “human giants”

5.2.2

How would an Earth with giant humans look?

5.2.3

Miracles as refuge

5.2.4

How to move forward

6

Future prospects

6.1

Unanswered questions

6.2

A universal framework for science-hadith reconciliation


Looking forward to y'all's thoughts and comments on it!

Wednesday, January 19, 2022

Framing the debate on human origins: misconceptions and burden of proof

 0. Why

In this post, I’ll be attempting to clarify an important misconception about evolutionary reasoning. In the process, we’ll hopefully get a clear idea of what the shape of the human origins debate should be – who has what burden of proof, and why. One can consider this as a framing/prequel to my last article on how to explain the evidence for evolution. This post doesn’t really add anything substantive to the old article, just sets up the appropriate framing for it.

As a helpful teaching tool, I’ll be using this YouTube video from Stated Clearly on the evidence for evolution. The video is an extremely well-made presentation of perhaps the best argument for human-chimp common descent – the presence of endogenous retroviral elements in our genomes. I suggest the reader watch the video first before reading the rest of this article. It should be kept in mind, however, that the comments of the article apply not just to the specific claims in the video – but really, virtually all of common descent reasoning.

So here’s what we’ll be doing in this post. First I’ll talk in detail about what the video gets wrong – specifically, two gaps in their argument. The next section, however, will comprise the video’s redemption arc: I’ll argue that these gaps in logic, if framed correctly, are trivial and can be plugged in easily. This section basically represents the “steelmanning” of common descent. In the last section, we’ll discuss our approach to defeat this stronger argument for common descent, using an analogy with another contentious topic in philosophy of religion.

1. Gaps in common descent reasoning
Or, What Stated Clearly stated somewhat ambiguously

In brief, the video presents an effective example of what I referred to as the problem of gratuitous similarities. Endogenous retroviral sequences are elements in the genome that are shared between humans and chimps. Not only are their sequences similar, but these elements are found in the exact same spots in the human and chimp genomes. Plus, not many of them have been proven to be functional. In fact, since these elements are essentially carcasses of viruses that once infected the host, it’s reasonable to assume prima facie that at least some of them are exactly what it says on the tag – broken, non-functional remains of viruses, not functional genetic elements. But even if they do turn out to be functional, it’s difficult to argue that these exact sequences in the exact genomic locations were necessary for functionality of this sort. Meaning, this similarity between humans and chimps is gratuitous – it cannot be explained by appealing to their shared utility alone. This is also called non-adaptive similarities in the literature: the similarity in itself has no adaptive benefit.

After laying out this data – and let me just go ahead and say the science here is perfectly solid - the video moves in for its central argument. It’s worth quoting this section in full (forgive the redundancy):

If humans and chimps share a common ancestor and if at least some of the infections we find in our genome occurred before the chimp-human split, we should find the same virus genes in the exact same locations in both human and chimp genomes. In contrast, if humans and chimps are not related, they should not share the same history of virus infections. . . [Scientists] found that [humans and chimps] share . . . two hundred and five [endogenous retroviral insertions] out of two hundred and fourteen [insertions] for this particular virus group. This makes perfect sense if we consider the evolutionary view of life. The two hundred and five viruses were inserted some time before the chimp-human split. . . In contrast, if we want to believe the fixed species view, we’re forced to conclude that these viruses are simply shared by coincidence. When we do the math . . . the chance of this happening by coincidence is less than one in [5.88 X 10^1418]. This evidence should be enough for the most reluctant yet rational person to carefully set aside the fixed species view. . . What we’ve seen here is just the tip of the iceberg. There are many other lines of DNA evidence available, together they demonstrate beyond all reasonable doubt that humans and chimpanzees did evolve from a common ancestor.

The “fixed species view” is code for Divine special creation – after all, unchanged species don’t just appear all of a sudden, they have to be miracled into existence supernaturally. I assume the video kept this language out of their presentation to remain religiously neutral, but the connection is unmistakable. For my purposes and for clarity, I’ll be re-stating the video’s claims in the more explicit God-language from now on.

There are two things I want to point out about this reasoning -

  1. The argument here makes assumptions about what a “fixed species view” - i.e. Divine special creation – would look. To put it more bluntly, the video is claiming, without any warrant, that God would not create humans and chimps with the genomes they in fact have. In fact, if God created fixed species, their genomes would look a certain way (random). The video seems to be engaging in a bit of theology in the guise of science.
  2. The conclusion that’s being drawn based on gratuitous similarity is common ancestry, but as we’ll see – it should more appropriately be to a common cause.

Let’s explore these points in turn.

1.1. Common descent as a theological explanation

I’m sure that the readership of this blog has heard the phrase “Nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evolution”. This sentence, especially oft-quoted in the context of evolution-creation debates, is the title of a journal article by the geneticist Theodosius Dobzhansky. The paper itself has been cited with abandon, and it’s often one of the first assigned readings in an evolution class to acquaint folks with the evidence for evolution.

When I first read this paper a couple years ago, I was surprised at how theological it was. The author professes quite clearly that he’s a believing Christian, going so far as to say that he’s a creationist and an evolutionist – meaning, he believes evolution is God’s preferred way of creating biodiversity (a position we’d call theistic evolutionism nowadays). As for the arguments for evolution themselves, virtually all of them are in the general shape of – we find pattern X in nature, X can be explained by process A or process B, but process B is impossible because God would never do it that way. In this context, process A is natural evolution, process B is supernatural fiat. Here are three of the first quotes I found in the article that demonstrates this:

“[B]ut what a senseless operation it would have been, on God's part, to fabricate a multitude of species ex nihilo and then let most of them die out!”

“Was the Creator in a jocular mood when he made Psilopa petrolei for California oil-fields and species of Drosophila to live exclusively on some body-parts of certain land crabs on only certain islands in the Caribbean?”

“[Creationists] must insist that He [God] deliberately arranged things exactly as if his method of creation was evolution, intentionally to mislead sincere seekers of truth.”

And so on. God wouldn’t do things this way, the argument goes, so things must not have happened this way. The argument the paper seems to be making is unmistakably theological.

The Stated Clearly video represents Dobzhansky on steroids. Let’s consider the odds they mention at the end of their video: human and chimp viral elements lining up by coincidence. Why are we calculating odds for this view? Because this is what the video believes a “fixed species view” would predict: If humans and chimps were indeed fixed species (i.e. if they were miraculously brought about in that way), their endogenous retroviral elements would be random, meaning their lining up in the way that they do would be nothing but a brute coincidence. Of course, these odds look pathetic compared to common ancestry, especially since we know how retroviral infections happen and are retained through generations.

If you think about it, this is some pretty heavy-handed theological speculation. The video isn’t just claiming that God – the presumable Author of “fixes species” - would decidedly not create humans and chimps with shared endogenous retroviral elements, but goes one step further to claim if God created us, such elements would be randomly strewn about in our genomes.

Of course, there’s something peculiar about this line of reasoning – for one, they seem to only be able to justify common descent at the expense of supernatural creation, which entails dabbling in theology. Could they not have presented the evidence for common descent on its own? Must there be such a comparison with supernatural alternatives to make a positive case for common descent?

The answer to this question is yes. Actually, it’s almost trivially the case.

One might think that this conclusion is too strong – Dobzhansky’s article, for example, was written to convince a lay, churchgoing audience; plus the journal where the article appeared was more of a teaching journal than a research one (The American Biology Teacher) - so the author can definitely be forgiven for indulging in a few rhetorical flourishes in such a context. However, despite those considerations, what Dobzhansky lays out is in fact the argument for common descent – presented in a rhetorically effective, lay-friendly way to be sure.

The argument for common descent between two or more creatures – between humans and chimpanzees, say – is essentially a comparison between likelihoods. Observation A is more probable on hypothesis B than it is on hypothesis C. Observation A obtains. We’re therefore more warranted in accepting hypothesis B than hypothesis C. In the case of common descent, the observation is gratuitous similarities, e.g. endogenous retroviral elements.

This sort of contrastive explanation is at the heart of common descent reasoning. More strongly, a case for common descent cannot be made without making an inter-hypothesis comparison. This is an important point, because a popular misconception is that the evidence for common descent is somehow intrinsic to the data – that we can somehow “read off” the theory of common descent from the gratuitous similarities we find in nature. In fact, two organisms being gratuitously similar to each other, taken on its own, is only consistent with them having a shared ancestry. Given no other information, the shared pattern of viral elements is consistent with infections in the common ancestor of humans and chimps. But for the hypothesis to have justifying reasons for acceptance, that likelihood needs to be compared with other, competing explanations to show that it’s superior. In our case, the competing explanation is special creation, or “fixed species” view as Stated Clearly put it. This would, in turn, mean calculating odds about what would the world look if God was acting supernaturally.

For a thorough demonstration of the need for such a theological comparison, I refer the reader to papers like this and this, where the authors show that contrasting with creationist hypotheses is how common descent has always been justified; that it’s fundamental to the logic of the argument, and not merely a rhetorical flourish. I cite papers to demonstrate this point, but really, it should be something obvious and uncontroversial. Let’s say you find feature X shared between humans and chimps that serve no adaptive purpose, and you think this suggests common ancestry. However, I can very easily counter that claim by saying: hold on, how do you know God didn’t create humans and chimps separately with shared feature X? The only way to move forward in this conversation for the common descent proponent is to show that the separate creation hypothesis is explanatorily inferior – i.e. that there’s some reason to go with the common descent hypothesis than the special Divine action one. That might be easy or hard, but the point is that obstacle needs to be removed for the common descent inference to go through.

Is that a problem? We’ll return to that shortly, but let’s look at the second gap in the video’s logic.

1.2. Equivocating common cause with common ancestor

The philosopher of science Eliot Sober painstakingly lays out the logic of evolutionary inferences in his book Evidence and Evolution: The Logic behind the Science. In the chapter on common descent, for example, he shows why similarities between organisms are evidence for common descent through a 9-step Bayesian decomposition. However, careful logician as he is, Sober also mentions this curious detail afterwards:

There are three ways in which a similarity observed to unite organisms X and Y might trace back to a common cause:

  • ·       The common cause is a common ancestor.
  • ·       The common cause is an organism though not a common ancestor.
  • ·       The common cause is not an organism.

The second of these possibilities might involve lateral gene transfer; the third would be true if X and Y originated from the same slab of rock but lacked a common ancestor. When the human beings and chimps alive now share a characteristic (and propositions 1–9 are true), this is evidence that there was a common cause. But what characteristics did that common cause have? Biologists do not doubt that it was an organism, but they go much farther – it was an animal, a vertebrate, a mammal, and a primate.

Sober, therefore, distinguishes two steps in the common descent inference: one, establishing a common cause; and two, identifying what that common cause is. Meaning, the similarities between humans and chimps, strictly speaking, only show that these two organisms share a common cause. However, it might be that this common cause is “some slab of rock”. Maybe – as in it’s logically possible that - there’s a slab of rock with magical properties, which can produce similar organisms like humans and chimps. However, Sober quickly moves away from such a possibility and concludes that we know that there were no magic rock involved, and in fact the common cause was a biological common ancestor.

One might think that we’re being pedantic by talking about magic rocks, and they might be right. But it’s important to acknowledge that this gap in logic exists. Here’s Sober a few pages back, being even more explicit about the two separate steps of the common ancestry inference:

The first order of business is to determine whether there was a common cause. If the answer is yes, the second question is whether that common cause was a common ancestor, an organism that was not a common ancestor, or no organism at all. [emphasis in original]

To sum up, then, any argument from gratuitous similarities – including the one presented by the video – can only go so far as to establish that these organisms have a common cause, not that they had a shared biological ancestor. So why is it that scientists, Sober and our friends at Stated Clearly are so confident in concluding that the common cause is “an animal, a vertebrate, a mammal, and a primate” as opposed to “some slab of rock”? Is this inference significant?

As it happens…

2. All of this is trivial

The reader might be willing to grant that these are indeed gaps in the video’s logic – it assumes too much about what God might do (i.e. what “fixed species” would look like), and conflates common cause with common ancestor. In what the cool kids call an epic twist, I’ll now demonstrate that the common descent proponent need not lose sleep over this, since the gaps are trivial and can be filled with some smart framing.

First, however, I need to make clear that these two gaps in fact represent the same problem. For the first one, the common descent proponent is assigning probabilities to God’s supernatural action. Likewise for the second, the hasty move from cause to ancestor also represents some assigning of probabilities: the idea being, the odds of God having caused two gratuitously similar species are lower than that of common ancestry leading to such an outcome. Put differently, the common cause being God (or to use Sober’s example, some slab of rock) is lower than the common cause being a primate ancestor. So while the gap in logic can be fleshed out in two ways, both of them involve the same thing: assigning probabilities to the God hypothesis.

In other words still, the charge we’re hurling against our common ancestry proponent is: they need to justifiably “rule out” (i.e. probabilistically) supernatural Divine action before his inference can move through. Dobzhansky and Stated Clearly, as well as evolutionary inferences in general, don’t seem to be providing such justification, and instead taking these theological views for granted.

Conceptualized this way, this demand seems to be quite trivial.

Imagine, if you will, that we find a pawprint in the sand, and want to conclude that this has been made by an animal with paws. Now imagine the irritation we must feel if our pedantic philosopher friend appears from behind the bushes and says – ah, but is it not possible that God supernaturally arranged the local structure of the sand in such a way which would resemble a paw? Are you really warranted in moving ahead with the pawprint hypothesis before refuting the special-paw-shaped-sand-hole-creation hypothesis? One might argue that we’re doing something very similar in the case of the common descent inference.

And so, the response goes, there might indeed be a leap in logic in popular common ancestry inferences, but it’s trivial and filled readily. Let’s use this line of thought to steelman common descent inferences.

2.1. Steelmanning common descent

The question of whether the triviality problem is a genuine one, I think, boils down to how probabilities are assigned to the Divine special creation hypothesis.

One is the way Theodosius Dobzhansky and Stated Clearly do it – to say that such probability (i.e. of God creating gratuitously similar creatures) is low (actually, non-existent. For Stated Clearly, fixed species means Divine action means completely random viral elements. For Dobzhansky, even the suggestion is blasphemous). I think this is actually a pretty strong claim – by saying that God would not do things in a certain way, we’re engaging in substantive theological reasoning. Not only are we claiming to know things about God’s character, we’re also claiming that such character is inconsistent with acting in a certain way.

I think this is an unnecessarily difficult route for the common descent arguer to take. This is because, all the creationist would need to do to counter this claim is to show that, for all we know, God might have reason for allowing gratuitous similarity in nature. These don’t even have to be good reasons necessarily, but just reasons we can’t confidently state are bad.

As an example, consider this argument made in a biology textbook, quoted in this paper I cited above:

An engineer would never use the same underlying structure to design a grasping tool, a digging implement, a walking device, a propeller, and a wing. Instead, the structural homology exists because mammals evolved from the lungfish-like ancestor that had the same general arrangement of bones in its fins.

Really, all one would need to do to counter this claim is to show that some engineer might not never do such a thing. One can point to Richard Owen for example, the British naturalist contemporary to Darwin, who basically did all of the hard work of unearthing patterns of homology in vertebrate bone structures but, came to a very non-naturalistic conclusion. According to him, these similarities pointed to some primeval archetype – either a pantheistic force of nature, or plan in a Divine mind – on which the design of organisms is based. So here we do have an example of someone showing that God might have some design-theoretic reasons for creating a grasping tool, a digging implement, a propeller, and a wing out of the same underlying structure. Regardless of whether that’s a good reason or not, this possibility means one can no longer claim that an engineer would “never” create biodiversity in this way.

As mentioned above, the route taken by the Stated Clearly video coincides with this. The only thing one would need to do to counter their assertion is to provide a marginally plausible reason as to why God might not create fixed species completely randomly. For example, similarity between creatures has aesthetic value, and by making human and chimp genomes similar to each other – God is increasing the aesthetic value of creation, even though the arrangement itself isn’t adaptive. Alternatively, consider the old school great chain of being idea – apparently God created all possible forms of biology, so on this “chain of being”, there would be things that look almost exactly alike. If I’m not wrong, the first reports of chimpanzee sighting were met with positivity for this very reason: ah, finally, another link in God’s great chain of being. On this view of creation, then, the fact that humans look so similar with chimpanzees actually has a high probability. I’m not saying these are good responses by any means, but it just goes to show that strong claims about Divine motivations are ill-advised and easy to shoot down.

So this, I think, is a non-starter for the common descent proponents. A much simpler (and I think more convincing) approach is to adopt what Dilley and Tafacory call indeterminate theology. This approach wouldn’t say that God has no reasons for allowing gratuitous similarities, but would only claim that we don’t know how God would do things. He might allow gratuitous similarities, or He might not, but there’s no reason to prefer either possibility above the other. I think this sort of skeptical theistic approach has a much more manageable burden of proof.

Consider this quote from another evolution textbook, again quoted in the same paper:

Similarity of structure despite differences in function follows from the hypothesis that the characteristics of organisms have been modified from the characteristics of their ancestors, but it is hard to reconcile with the hypothesis of intelligent design. Design does not require that the same bony elements form the frame of the hands of primates, the digging forelimbs of moles, the wings of bats, birds, and pterosaurs, and the flippers of whales and penguins. [emphasis mine]

The authors are being extremely careful in their wording. They’re not saying a Designer would not create things this way, but only that – there’s no reason to think that He would (i.e. Design “does not require” that these things obtain). He might, or He might not, we’re in no position to adjudicate. The great chain of being might be a thing, or it might not. The probability of gratuitous similarity on a special creation hypothesis, then, is indeterminate. On the other hand, the probability of such features on common descent is decent. Faced with the choice of two hypotheses – one with a knowable, high likelihood and the other with an indeterminate one – we would be warranted in accepting the former over the latter.

I think this argument is convincing as far as it goes. This is also the argument made by Sober against a certain formulation of Intelligent Design in his book Evidence and Evolution. In order for a hypothesis to be successful, really, for it to get off the ground – we need to be able to assign probabilities to it. But if God’s reasons are inscrutable, and we have no idea whether He would create earthly biodiversity in a certain way over others, then that’s essentially a death knell to any design inference. More relevant to our case, if we don’t know if God would have any motivation either way to allow gratuitous similarities between humans and chimps, then that’s a battle common descent would win easily – because common descent does give us reasons to suspect such patterns.

If the argument for common descent in framed in these terms, I would agree that the gaps become trivial and the inference goes through. If you’re not convinced, consider the pawprint case: it might be somewhat weird for someone to claim to have positive reasons as to why God might not allow a footprint in the sand, but such weirdness would be amplified further in a human origins discussion. For whatever reason – be it sociological or religious biases or otherwise – humanity is really hesitant to say God would have no reason to become supernaturally involved in an event like the origin of humans. In the language of probability, we’re more confident in assigning a low probability to the Divine action hypothesis in the pawprint case, than we are in the human origins case. So if that’s the burden of proof the creationist is supposed to meet, I would think it would be met rather easily. A more clever tack would be just to profess ignorance: God might have reasons to become supernaturally involved in creating gratuitously similar organisms or a pawprint in the sand, but we have no idea if He does. Let’s keep theology indeterminate.

With this change in framing, it seems like the common descent argument has indeed been vindicated. Unless.

3. The solution is a theodicy

One of the most discussed arguments in philosophy of religion is the problem of suffering: the idea that God would not allow (at least certain kinds of) pain and suffering in the world. It’s important to note that even if the argument were successful, it wouldn’t lead to atheism per se. The argument only attempts to show that a deity in charge of our affairs cannot have certain attributes – they cannot be powerful enough to prevent the occurrence of suffering, or benevolent enough to have the intention to do so. The problem of suffering is consistent with certain forms of deism, for instance, the idea that the creator of the universe doesn’t really care very much about our pains and pleasures. So what the problem of suffering targets is not God, but God’s providence – His protective care over His creation (of course, one could argue whether such an amoral or non-omnipotent God even deserves the name to begin with, since the God of theism is defined as the greatest possible being. But still, one would hardly call belief in a deistic “god” atheism). Put differently, the argument targets one type of divine action (providence), while leaving other types of action unscathed (creation and sustenance).

The most popular versions of this argument are probabilistic (also called evidential): the occurrence of widespread pain and suffering has a low probability on the hypothesis of Divine providence. However, it has a decent probability on the “indifferent universe/deity” hypothesis: pain and suffering, after all, are readily explicable as parts of the natural biological responses of animals. This means we should probably opt for the second hypothesis.

I hope the analogies with the common descent problem are clear. Like the problem of suffering, the common descent hypothesis is aimed at a particular type of Divine action: special creation of humans. And like the problem of evil, it also involves assigning probabilities to the Divine action hypothesis.

So, how do the theistic philosophers of religion respond to the problem of evil?

By far the most popular tack is to demonstrate that God, in His providence, in fact has a decent probability of allowing pain and suffering in the world. This is not merely skeptical theism – this is not saying for all we know God could’ve had reasons to allow suffering. Rather, the theist here is making a stronger claim: given what we know about God’s character, we would actually expect Him to allow suffering in the world to attain some of His purposes.

I think in the common descent discussion, the proponent of special Divine action needs to accept a similar burden of proof. We need to demonstrate that the probability of gratuitously similar organisms, far from being low or indeterminate, is in fact high on a special Divine action hypothesis. In other words, given what we know about God’s character and motivations, this sort of pattern in nature is exactly what we should expect. That’s what effectively blocks the common descent inference.

A theodicy, essentially. Of course, I attempted to develop just such a theodicy in my most recent article on the blog.

That’s pretty much all I wanted to say in this framing post, but one other thought for general consideration: in addition to explaining the evidence for common ancestry on a special Divine action hypothesis, we would also be benefited from a positive case for the hypothesis: i.e. observations that are readily explained on a uniquely supernatural human origin scenario, but unlikely on a naturalistic common ancestry one. I might write more in the future about such approaches.

Really, really old models of Adamic origins

Young Earth Creationist (YEC) thinkers believe most if not all species in the Homo  genus comprise the species of Adam (e.g.  here ,  here ,...